Wednesday, April 29, 2015

1) Engaging the Problem of Evil: Preface

               The essay you are about to read was written as my final paper in my Honors Bible class.  At first, I intended it to be a mere summary of my previously posted essay, “A Response to the Problem of Evil”, with a few useful, albeit less impactful, new insights added to cover the space remaining after that summary.  But after honestly thinking it through and writing the essay as thoughtfully as I could, I ended up bringing out insights which I thought to be rather enlightening, and I desire greatly to publish those insights.  Furthermore, this essay has a much different tone in comparison to the former; the first half, which merely summarizes “A Response to the Problem of Evil”, is intellectual, but the second half is more pastoral.  I have always been taught, through my Honors Bible class, that there are two halves to the whole problem of evil: the logical problem and the emotional problem.  Unlike my previous essay on the matter, which largely addressed only the former problem, this essay intends to address each problem in turn.

2) Engaging the Problem of Evil: Introduction

               I can see it now – a meme which communicates with wit and wisdom the problem with which we are currently confronted, “One does not simply: solve the problem of evil.”  I therefore do not set out to, in this single essay, solve – with irrevocable decisiveness – the problem of pain and evil in the world.  That is simply an impossibility.   But even if we cannot solve the problem of evil, perhaps we can at minimum engage it, or somehow do something to mitigate it.  We might just as soon try to swim up a waterfall, but we will try it all the same.  Have you something better to do?  Do you rather recommend that we shut up, take it, and give up?  I’ll not be struck down so easily, even by so surpassingly great a problem.  Having been equipped with a few philosophical tricks by the highly recommendable book God and Evil, in addition to plenty of personal experience, the following is my engagement of the problem of evil.

3) Engaging the Problem of Evil: The "Standard "Argument

               First off, it seems to me rather obvious that the existence God cannot be objected to on evil’s account.  Quite the contrary: evil cannot exist unless our beginning assumption is that God exists.  I have already argued this more extensively elsewhere[1], and it is not the first time that such an argument has been presented[2].  For now, we’ll have to do with a sharp and concise summary of that argument, due to space constraints.
                It seems to me obvious that evil requires some standard of good; evil might be perfectly and completely described as non-good, and in order to do that, we need some standard of what good is.  If evil is that which is undesirable, we need a standard of what is desirable.  If evil is injustice, we need a standard of justice.  What we are interested with at present is the particular qualities that this standard must possess in order to make sense of evil.
                First off, is the standard objective or subjective?  Is it wholly independent of what others think about it or is it wholly determined by what people make of it?  We can clearly conclude it to be the former for three reasons: 1) if evil is subjective, the Atheist’s objection against God on its account falls flat on the floor.  I have a few more insights to supply about this later.  2) There is not a person on earth who thinks that he is perfect; the one who does, we call “insane”.  As such, there is in fact no person capable of properly judging what is and is not evil.  The standard which judges whether or not something is evil cannot itself contain a shred of evil; if it did, then by what standard should we say that that standard had been judged to contain evil?  We’d have an endless recession of almost-but-not-quite-good standards.  The imperfection of man proves that there is some standard of good undetermined by man himself from which he has fallen short.  3) If something is perfectly subjective, then it does not exist.  What I mean to say in relation to goodness is that there can be no coherent idea of goodness if it is perfectly subjective to what someone says about it.  Picture a world full of mirrors and only mirrors.  Boggling as it is to realize, such a world has no color.  The color in this world is perfectly subjective, but until any objective color is introduced, there is still no color.
                Second, is the objective standard natural or supernatural?  Clearly the latter.  When the Atheist says that evil exists, it is more accurate to say that he is saying that evil exists in the natural world.  Note that this means that the whole natural world is being compared to a standard of good.  And if the standard itself also exists in the natural world, we make the following claims:
                1. Everything in the natural world is being compared to an objective standard of good
                2. The objective standard of good is in the natural world
                3. Therefore, the objective standard of good is being compared to itself
                It is imperative that we opt out of this argument because its conclusion is an absurdity; something cannot be compared to itself simply by virtue of what comparison is.  We cannot say that the conclusion does not logically follow – the argument is valid.  Now, are the premises true?  Clearly, we cannot deny premise (1).  If mankind were to, say, fly billions of light years to another planet and populate there, surely evil would still be a problem.  There is, however, no good reason why we cannot deny premise (2) by stating that the objective standard of good is, in fact, in the supernatural world.  We therefore conclude that the objective standard of good is supernatural.
                One last qualifier must be brought up for this objective, supernatural standard.  One thing which it makes us aware of is moral evil.  The standard, therefore, must be a measure of moral good.  But moral evil is, in fact, an abuse of free will; moral evil does not exist in the absence of free will.  Furthermore, you cannot be morally good without free will; someone who does something good mechanistically is not being morally good.  We are therefore forced to conclude that the objective, supernatural standard has a will of its own, and it always uses this will for good.  Otherwise, we wouldn’t know that man’s will was off kilter.
                In conclusion, we have an objective, supernatural standard of good with a will of its own.  In other words, we have the theistic God!




[1] see my entries under February 28, 2015 on blogofangrymen.blogspot.com
[2] see especially essays 14 and 15 in God and Evil

4) Engaging the Problem of Evil: the Pain of Evil Argument

               Another line of argumentation before changing moods.  In the paragraphs above, I said that Atheists cannot object to God’s existence on account of subjective evil.  I’d here like to unpack that concept a little further, because I believe that it can provide for us some serious and practical insights.  I here state that unless God is in the picture, evil does not hurt enough to object to God on its account.
                Now, in a world without God, evil might, at best, be decided some set of objective, immutable principles – much like the laws of physics and mathematics – which can be scrutinized by deeper human reason[1].  But if that is really all that evil is, then it does not hurt very much at all.  To say that Hitler, Stalin, etc. aligned their lives with this set of inherently “wrong” principles rather than that set of inherently “right” principles gives us a kind of evil which really isn’t very difficult to put up with.  You might just as soon be personally hurt and upset when an astrophysicist gets his sums wrong.  This kind of evil does not hurt enough to object to the theist’s worldview on its account.
But let’s just say, for the sake of argument, that there exists a single, immutable Omnibenevolence which has decreed man to be benevolent to his fellow creatures.  In such a world, evil would be very personal.  Not only would each act of evil be a trespass against the Omnibenevolence – it would be a gross trespass of man against his fellow man, especially since the Omnibenevolence decrees that he is being quite worthy of benevolence from his fellow creature.  Evil, in this model, is brutally defiant of Goodness itself and dehumanizing to the fellow man.
I want to make sure that these next points are extremely clear; their importance is instrumental in understanding the problem of evil.  If this model is true, then evil hurts enough for the Atheist to deny that God exists.  If the Atheists are right – if evil hurts as much as they say it does – then they have every right to challenge God’s existence.  I readily concede that.  But evil can only hurt as much as the Atheist says it does if this model is true, and if this model is true, then we know for a fact that God exists – he would be the Omnibenevolence, of course.  The Atheist can only object to God’s existence if evil hurts to x degree, but evil can only hurt to x degree if God exists[2]





[1] Note that this conception of morality does not well account for moral imperatives; again, see essays 14 and 15 in God and Evil for more discussion on this.
[2] Essay 13 in God and Evil unpacks insights similar to these arguments, “Only a fully biblical view of theism that upholds the purity and holiness of God and the irreparably devastating nature of evil can present the problem in all of its force.”

5) Engaging the Problem of Evil: a Rejoinder

Oh, how well the theist’s position is defended by the very thing which seeks to destroy it: evil!  In conclusion, it seems to me obvious that imperfection implies perfection.  If we are to say that the world is imperfect, we assume the existence of the perfect world (heaven).  If we are to say that people are imperfect, we assume the existence of the perfect Person (God).  If we are to say that relationships between persons are imperfect, we assume the existence of the perfect Relationship between perfect Persons (the Trinity).
Whether or not God exists, therefore, cannot be the center of the issue.  That question is thrown out; evil could not possibly hurt as much as it does unless there was some immutable, omnibenevolent God, and we were all, in any sense you wish to take it, a family under Him.  Evil could not rip our hearts out as much as it does without this sense of unification across persons and universal accountability before God.  What, therefore, is the center of the issue?  Why do Atheists struggle to trust God in the face of evil?
I have thought long and hard about this one, only to realize that I should not expect an answer.  Every Atheist has his reasons for objecting to God’s existence; indeed, even Christians do!  It’s not as if everyone will have the same reasons; to suggest otherwise is quite foolish.  But I do think that there are some underlying principles beneath the denial of God on evil’s account, and while it may indeed be true that a person honestly thinks that there is a logical tension between the existence of evil and a perfectly good God, this tension is so easily resolved that we can plainly see how it is not the center of the issue.  Clearly, the cardinal tension between God and evil is emotional.

6) Engaging the Problem of Evil: Defining the Emotional Problem

My investigation for the center (if not one of the many “centers”) of the problem of evil began with the recognition of a certain pattern within the internal dialogue of the book God and Evil itself.  A great many chapters followed the general shell of the Atheist claiming, “Clearly, no all-good, all-powerful God exists because blah blah blah,” followed by the Christian response, “I see what you mean, Mr. Atheist, but it is quite possible that God had perfectly good reasons for allowing blah blah blah.”[1]  It is noteworthy that we are not, in such instances, debating with hard-and-fast logic, but much more on the grounds of inductive reasoning and probability.  In other words, there is a surprising amount of subjectivity to the situation.  The Christian considers it quite plausible that God has his reasons; the Atheist does not.  One considers evil to be quite worth it; the other does not.
Who is right?  Technically, both are.  Bearing in mind that both positions acknowledge that God exists, since that is the required presupposition in order to get the concept of evil off the ground, each position on the “worth it” value of evil is, in fact, intellectually feasible.  A cynical theist has valid reasons for thinking that evil is not worth it.  The Christian has valid reasons for thinking to the contrary.  However, investigation should tell us that only the latter of the two positions is emotionally feasible.
Now, whatever we think of God, we are forced on all sides to acknowledge that he believed that evil was worth it.  Why so?  Consider if God created a world within which he knew that evil would emerge and further believed that evil would not be worth it in such a world.  Such a God would clearly not be omnibenevolent.  But hold – once again, we are bringing in some standard of omnibenevolence and comparing it to this less-than-perfect God.  We end up with an endless recession of almost-but-not-quite-good standards once again.  God is necessarily perfect; if he is imperfect, then he is being compared to a standard of perfection which is more worthy of being called “God”.  And in order for God to be perfect, he had to think that evil was worth it when he created a world within which evil emerged.
Therefore, the insistence of the cynical theist that evil is not worth it is revealed to be contrary to the analysis of a Being with far greater knowledge – infinitely greater knowledge, in fact – than the cynic.  This simply won’t do.  If a Being with infinite knowledge makes an assessment on something, the attempt of a being with pitifully less knowledge to make a different assessment on the matter demonstrates a degree of arrogance, despair, cynicism, and denial capable of tearing the soul asunder.  A theist should think that evil is worth the accompanied good, not because the position is more intellectually true than the other, but because doing so demonstrates an emotionally healthy degree of humility and self-knowledge.  The fact of the matter is that if God, a Being of infinite perfection and wisdom, thought that evil was worth it, then I, a being of imperfection and fallible knowledge, should probably agree.
We therefore conclude that the emotional problem of evil results when one disagrees with God about whether or not evil is worth it, and is solved when that individual realizes that only agreement with God in regards to evil can steer one clear of being emotionally shipwrecked by arrogance, despair, and the like.
This is a summary of the issue: the acknowledgment of evil logically requires the acknowledgment of God.  But it does not logically require one to agree with God’s decisions regarding evil.  If the logic has been demonstrated to a man, yet still he holds to the conviction that evil is not worth it, he is sold to his pride and anger towards God and, more depressingly, his despair towards evil.  He has thrown up his hands, thrown in the towel, cried Uncle; he has simply and decisively given up and surrendered to the problem of evil.  The Christian, on the other hand, has accepted that evil is worth it and that God has his reasons.  He too has, in a sense, given up, but not towards the horror of evil as opposed to the wisdom of God.  It is the latter, and not the former, who has the fortitude required to thrive in the face of evil.





[1] the first 10 chapters of God and Evil follow this pattern particularly closely, with other chapters sharing this posture to varying degrees

7) Engaging the Problem of Evil: Conclusion

I conclude with one last pastoral reflection.  The fourth paragraph up, I argued that God had to have believed that evil was worth it in order to qualify as perfect.  That argument was made on the assumption that it is, in fact, metaphysically possible for evil to outdo good in terms of worth.  I’m not so certain that this is even a metaphysical possibility.  A single shred – the tiniest grain of true joy – is worth even an infinity of evil and transgression.  If there is no good, then there can be no evil, and if there is even a shred of true good, then no amount of evil that results can overturn it.  The Psalmist seemed to express similar sentiments, “Better is one day in your courts than a thousand elsewhere” (Ps. 84:10 NIV).  C. S. Lewis, through the characters in his narrative The Great Divorce, communicates insights that are well in agreement:
And yet all loneliness, angers, hatreds, envies and itchings that [Hell] contains, if rolled into one single experience and put into the scale against the least moment of the joy that is felt by the least in Heaven, would have no weight that could be registered at all.  Bad cannot succeed even in being bad as truly as good is good.  If all Hell’s miseries together entered the consciousness of yon wee yellow bird on the bough there, they would be swallowed up without trace, as if one drop of ink had been dropped into that Great Ocean to which your terrestrial Pacific itself is only a molecule.[1]
                There is, therefore, reason for optimism.  For we are in the hands of some kind of Something which we have an idea in our minds about; something which, through our knowledge of it, allows us to discern that our world is truly fallen.  And if it is fallen, then there is a Height from which it fell.  And if there is a Height from which it fell, then we must entertain the hope of returning to that Height, or else perish in absolute despair.  Christianity presents to us a chilling story of this fall, a maddening picture of the Height from which we fell (maddening because it is so surpassingly beautiful), and a glorious hope in the Resurrection, through which we might rise up from the depths into which we have fallen through the divine enigma that is Christ.





[1] see Lewis 138-139

8) Engaging the Problem of Evil: Works Cited

Meister, Chad and James K. Dew Jr.  God and Evil.  Downers Grove: InterVarsity Press, 2013.  Print

Lewis, C. S.  The Great Divorce.  New York: Harper Collins, 2001.  Print.

New International Version.  Korea: Holman Bible Publishers, 1999.  Print.