Sunday, January 25, 2015

3) Calvinism and Armenianism: An Analysis of Armenianism

               There is perhaps nothing more opposite than Calvinism and Armenianism.  For while Calvinism contends that God has the future exhaustively settled, Armenianism contends that God has not settled the future.  He has left it open to leave room for human free will; we all have the option to do “this or that” precisely because God has not decided nor does he know what will happen in the future.  Now, most Armenianists will tell you that God has a rough framework for where he wants this world to go.  But he does not know precisely how these events will come to pass.  You could say that God and men share in their control of the future; God because of his superior power and wisdom, and men because God has given them the gift of free will and the freedom to exercise it.
                Armenianism is strong where Calvinism is weak.  It presents to us a clear explanation of the origin of evil.  We have free will, since God neither controls us nor decides our future, and we used it for evil deeds.  To explain why God endowed us with the ability to do evil at all, Armenianism can always remind us that without the ability to do evil, we would not have the ability to do good, either.  Love that is forced, for instance, is not really love at all.  The ability to love comes with the ability to hate simply by definition.
                But coincidentally, Armenianism is also weak where Calvinism is strong.  While it leaves ample room for evil and free will, it is unable to attribute to God the amount of power and knowledge which he is due.  Armenianists will protest this to the grave, so I had better give my reasons.
                Whatever we suppose about God, we ought to suppose that he cannot fail, not simply because so many theologians before us have insisted as much, but because we realize that it makes sense after thinking about it for long enough.  If God fails, then according to whose standard has he failed?  His own?  In that case, how could he remain God if he has fallen short of his own standard?  Wouldn’t the standard, then, be what we call “God” instead, since God has fallen short of it?  Thus, we conclude that God cannot fail.  The problem is that, according to the Armenianist account, God can fail.  He has left the future open, and as such, he does not know what will happen in that future.  He has an “outline”, if you will, communicating a general idea of where he wants history to go, but even he cannot guarantee that it will come to pass.
                Armenianists hasten to point out that though God can fail, he won’t fail.  He is often compared to a master chess player so skilled at chess that he can anticipate every move his opponent (in this case, the Devil) might make, and, more importantly, the ideal response to any move his opponent makes.  Note in passing, however, that God still only knows what his opponents might do.  I’m sure I don’t know why, but Armenianists staunchly deny God the surety of what his opponents will do.  And if God does not know for certain what his opponents will do, then how can he guarantee us that he certainly will succeed?  The best he can offer is that he might succeed, for that is all he can anticipate about his opponents’ moves.
                Armenianists are like to slough this point off on account of their belief that God knows what people very probably will do.  In other words, he knows with 99.999…% certainty that person A will freely choose B given circumstances C.  Two things.  First, while this contention does make it look extremely likely that God will succeed, it does not remove the merit of my previous contention.  There is still only a 99.999…% chance of that he will succeed, and a 0.000…1% chance that he will fail.  To be considered theologically coherent, Armenianism, if it cannot tell us that God cannot fail, should at least be able to guarantee us that God won’t fail.  But it cannot even do this. 
Second, this idea actually exposes another flaw with the Armenianist God; namely, a flaw in omniscience.  Now, in order to qualify as omniscient, we ought to say that God must, at minimum, know whatever he knows completely.  It is almost self-evident that he would not know something only to a limited extent; for instance, if he knew about horses, he would not have knowledge only of its muscular system and lack knowledge of its skeletal system.  If he knew about horses, he would know every conceivable thing that there is to know about them; if he didn’t, then clearly knowledge would be missing from him, and he would not be omniscient.  But we see that the God of Armenianism does not fulfill this constraint of omniscience.  For God knows what people will do, but he does not know this completely; he knows it with 99.999…% surety but not quite 100% surety.  Such is the equivalent of God knowing 99.999…% of the facts there are to know about horses.
                The Armenianist will combat this by denying that what someone will do is a truth; they will contend that it cannot be known what someone will do, and thus, God does not need to know it in order to qualify as omniscient.  There are two more problems with this.  First, if what someone will do was not a truth and thus could not be known, then God would not know anything of it.  Speaking methodically: if something cannot be known, then God knows it with 0% certainty.  If something can be known, then God must know it with 100% certainty in order to qualify as omniscient (since omniscience requires that God knows whatever he knows completely).  He would not, if something could be known, know it with 99.999…% certainty.  Armenianists must decide whether or not God knows what someone will do with 0% certainty – in which case they hold that what someone will do is not a truth – or 100% certainty – in which case they hold that what someone will do is a truth.  Until one of the two is decided, the Armenianist God still does not obey the constraints of omniscience.
                Second, it is not even convincing to say that what someone will do is not a truth in the first place.  Namely, because everyday people with flawed knowledge in comparison to God can know it to a certain extent.  We can analyze patterns of behavior and predict, with weak but not invalid accuracy, what someone will do.  Armenianism, to escape the problem of insufficient knowledge in the God of its theology, must suppose that he knows with 0% surety what people will do; which would be very odd indeed in light of the fact that ordinary people can know this with some 25% surety or so (far more for psychologists).  Or they can suppose that God knows what people will do with 100% surety, at which point Armenianism collapses into a completely different theology known as Molinism, or Middle Knowledge, which is not discussed in this essay.   
                I acknowledge that the God of Armenianism has a 99.999…% chance of success.  But the fact that there is still a 0.000…1% chance of failure is simply theologically imprudent.  Where the rubber meets the road, God cannot guarantee that he cannot nor that he will not fail.  God ought not to be considered, “A thoroughly powerful being who is 99.999…% perfect.”  He ought to be, “The only being who is 100% perfect.”

No comments:

Post a Comment